Coase's Tortoise
By: Kevin WilliamsonPosted on April 16, 2014 National Review Topics:
Federal bureaucracy gets in the way of complex ongoing relationships that serve civil society.
If you want to see the case for limited government, consider that there’s a siege happening in some dusty corner of Nevada over tortoise welfare.
Cliven Bundy, a Nevada rancher currently engaged in a standoff with the federal government over grazing land that his family has used since the 19th century, is very likely to end up bankrupt, in prison, or dead. As it turns out, the Coase theorem breaks down when one side in the negotiation has a standing army and nothing to lose.
Mr. Bundy’s family has been grazing cattle on their allotment of federal land since the 1870s, and things went along fairly well until the desert tortoise showed up. The Mojave population of desert tortoises is listed as a threatened species, and it is a crime to touch, harm, or harass a wild desert tortoise. (If it seems to you that tortoise harassment should be something less than a national priority for these United States, you are not alone.) It is permissible to adopt tortoises in Nevada, because of course we have a tortoise-adoption program administered by the Bureau of Land Management, which places microchips in the backs of captive tortoises before handing them over to eager new tortoise-keepers — limit one per family. The BLM also has imposed various tortoise-friendly rules on federal lands, and thus Mr. Bundy’s problem: He refused to accept new conditions on his grazing allotment in 1993, and continued pasturing his cattle in defiance of the federal government. This being the United States, litigation ensued, which Mr. Bundy lost, with a 2013 court decision ruling finally in favor of federal tortoise mandates. Mr. Bundy figures he owes the feds some $300,000 in fees, fines, and interest, whereas Uncle Sam puts the figure at more than $1 million. The government has been sporadically seizing his cattle. He calls them “cattle thieves,” which still constitute fighting words in the West.
And it may come to a fight. The outlaw rancher is as of this writing surrounded by a growing detachment of heavily armed law-enforcement agents — the BLM would neither confirm nor deny the deployment of snipers — and with a crowd of more than 100 supporters gathered, he is making comparisons to Ruby Ridge and the Branch Davidian raid at Waco. The BLM says that the rancher’s use of the term “range war” is inflammatory, which of course it is, but then so is the presence of armed federal agents.
Mr. Bundy maintains some eccentric legal theories in support of his case, and examining them in detail would be both exhausting and beyond my scope of expertise. Let us assume that he is in the wrong, legally speaking, and that the feds are in the right. What should be done?
In his famous 1960 article “The Problem of Social Cost,” the most cited law-review article in American academic history, Ronald Coase, subsequently a Nobel laureate, considered the problem of externalities, property rights, negotiation, and legal rules. The most well-known hypothetical example he considered was almost precisely Mr. Bundy’s situation: a case of trespassing cattle. Coase argued that in an environment of free and easy negotiation, the most economically efficient outcome would be achieved irrespective of the question of formal legal rights. For example, if the cost of building a fence to keep in the cattle is less than the cost of the damage the cattle do to the crops of the farmer who lives next door, then the fence will be built regardless of who is “in the right.” If the legal rule says that it is the farmer’s responsibility to protect his own property, then he builds the fence if the cost of doing so is less than the cost of the damage to his crops — but not if the cost is greater. If the legal rule says that it is the rancher’s responsibility to control his cattle, then he also builds the fence if the cost of doing so is less than the cost of the damage to his neighbor’s crops — but not if it costs more. In the latter circumstance, it would be more economically efficient for him to pay restitution to the farmer. Which is to say, you end up with the same outcome regardless of the initial allocation of legal rights.
It’s a fascinating idea, and some years later the Yale law scholar R. C. Ellickson got it into his head to test out the Coase theorem in the very context Coase imagined: conflicts between ranchers and farmers, in this case in Shasta County, Calif. His report, “Of Coase and Cattle: Dispute Resolution among Neighbors in Shasta County,” is itself a minor masterpiece. Among Ellickson’s findings:
The Shasta County evidence indicates that Coase’s Farmer-Rancher Parable correctly anticipates that a change in the rule of liability for cattle trespass does not affect, for example, the quality of fences that separate ranches and farms. The Parable’s explanation for the allocative toothlessness of law is, however, exactly backward. The Parable’s explanation is that transaction costs are low and that parties respond to a new rule by agreeing to an exchange of property rights that perpetuates the prior (efficient) allocation of resources. The field evidence I gathered suggests that a change in animal trespass law indeed fails to affect resource allocation, not because transaction costs are low, but because transaction costs are high. Legal rules are costly to learn and enforce. Trespass incidents are minor irritations between parties who typically have complex continuing relationships that enable them readily to enforce informal norms. The Shasta County evidence indicates that under these conditions, potential disputants ignore the formal law.
There is much of interest in those observations, but consider those “complex continuing relationships.” Normal human beings with adult temperaments understand that life is a complex, messy, imperfect business, and that sometimes we have to make accommodation for one another. It is for this reason that modern American English contains the phrase “Don’t make a federal case out of it.” I do not know Mr. Bundy, but, assuming that he is a decent sort, I think it is very likely the case that this story would have gone very differently if one of his neighbors had approached him one afternoon and said, “Say, Cliven, I’m worried that your cattle might step on my tortoises, which are very dear to me. What could we do about that?” Practically every suburbanite with a yard and neighbors with dogs has experienced a comparable situation, as has every urbanite with boisterous neighbors or neighbors who seem to become hard of hearing when their favorite television shows are on. (Ahem.) Our first instinct is not, as a rule, to make a federal case out of it.
Unless your neighbor is the federal government, in which case it’s a federal case in every case. There’s no negotiating tortoise protections; they are simply handed down from on high, and, if you don’t like it and won’t agree to it, men will be dispatched to your home with guns to seize your property and to threaten or use physical violence to bring you into compliance. Those who follow the Murray Rothbard school of thought take that as an argument for anarchism, while our Hobbesian progressives take from this tension a complementary lesson: that those who would oppose the encroachments of government put us on the road to anarchy. And that’s where the Rothbardian Right and the Hobbesian Left agree: It’s Leviathan or anarchy.
But if we are willing to climb down from the comfortable perch of theory and dwell for a moment in the real world, this need not be an argument for either total submission to the state or total resistance to it. It is, rather, an argument for limited government. Prudence counsels that under current conditions obedience to civil authority should be the general rule, in the interest of keeping the peace, and that disputes between citizens and the state be handled through the usual assortment of voting, lobbying, protesting, agitating, etc. (This is one of the reasons that the Left’s attempts to restrict citizens’ ability to influence policy through things such as campaign donations, to say nothing of proposals to lock people up for unpopular political speech, are more dangerous than is appreciated: With those remedies diminished, open defiance becomes more attractive.) A norm of obedience to civil authority does not mean that the application of civil authority is wise or desirable in every case, that the expansion of civil authority should not be resisted, or that a reduction in the national footprint of government is not to be desired.
Put another way: The great majority of us can imagine extreme circumstances in which the government’s demand for obedience should be resisted — nobody wants to be a good German. At the same time, most of us can imagine cases in which obedience to civil authority should go without saying — there’s not much debate over laws against robbery and murder, and only a little more over the expectation that all able-bodied men should be expected to come to the aid of the government in the event of a foreign invasion or the like.
But what about everything in between those extremes? A great deal of debate about rules for the commercial use of government lands would be unnecessary if the government did not own so much land; Mr. Bundy’s grazing allotment, not to be uncharitable, isn’t exactly Yellowstone or Yosemite. The most sensible thing to do would have been to offer to sell it to him. In those “complex continuing relationships” that are the stuff of real life, there is room for negotiation and compromise. And there is more opportunity for those complex ongoing relationships as the political entity in question moves farther away from the faceless and monolithic powers that be in Washington to state and (especially) local authorities. Mr. Bundy, for example, has pronounced himself ready to submit to his county sheriff, but not to the BLM. The problem is that Leviathan’s entire business model is predicated on the belief that where national governmental power is projected it must in the end be considered absolute, that if we refuse to stand on our heads when the Department of Health and Human Services mandates it, then we are already over the abyss into total chaos. And at some margin that very well may hold true.
But tortoises?
— Kevin D. Williamson is roving correspondent for National Review.
This article originally appeared in National Review Online on April 10, 2014.
For more sides to the issue, check out some of these articles:
NEW APRIL 27, 2014: Cliven Bundy, Racism, Politics, and History
Why You Should Be Sympathetic to Cliven Bundy